On the Emergence of de facto Private Property under Social Ownership
*Note: this is a repost from an earlier, defunct blog of mine.
Part 1. The Emergence of Private Property
“Social ownership” is often posited as an alternative
system of property to the private property-based system that exists in most of
the world today. It is apparently believed that the abolition of legal private
property is the necessary and sufficient condition for the creation of a
non-capitalist society. However, I will argue here that de facto private ownership and markets can emerge in land, natural resources,
other capital, and surpluses, absent any legal enforcement of extrapersonal
property, purely as a result of legal recognition of self-ownership (that is,
the absence of coercion on individuals), even under a system of social
ownership. I will show that this is the case even if we assume inalienability
of one's decisions. I will also argue that the emergence of a market economy in
such a 'socialist' (based on 'social' ownership of the external world) setting
improves the material conditions of people living in such a setting. Finally, I
will argue the existence of states which enforce contracts' between individuals
that 'alienate' the activity of their participants (i.e., enforces punishment
for refusal to do something one promised to do in a contract, be it the
rendering of labor or exchange of a good) merely expedites the development or expansion
of markets rather than creating them, and that perhaps even the existence of
such states can be explained (theoretically, not necessarily historically - the
latter would require more research than I have done, though it's possible
others have done it already) as a response to the transaction costs inherent in
a stateless (purely voluntary) market.
To reach this conclusion, let us first start from the
premise that all property is owned 'socially.' That is, everyone legally enjoys
the equal right to make use of any land, natural resource, or surplus goods
produced therefrom by anyone else. One may imagine that there is a state that
simply does not enforce any private property rights, or that there is anarchy.
As before, we will not even assume the enforcement of what we might call
'alienability.' That is, the purchase or sale of another person's action or
inaction is unenforcable. In the extreme case, alienability allows for selling
oneself into slavery. In more moderate cases, it might allow for the enforcable
sale of one's labor (e.g. wage labor). Here, we will assume that no alienable
exchange whatsoever is enforced: one may purport to sell the promise of one’s
labor for the following day to another person in exchange for their labor
today, then, after they’ve fulfilled their end of the bargain, renege and
refuse to work for them the following day, and the state would not intervene.
In our hypothetical 'socially owned' world, let's suppose a
farmer realizes that an innovation can be made that will increase his
productivity. He may realize, for example, that by letting his plots lay fallow
for one fourth of his crop rotations, even though he will reduce productivity
from that plot for that rotation, by mitigating soil depletion, this increases average
productivity in the long run. Two problems, however, face this innovative
farmer in a social ownership setting: 1) others will have an incentive to plant
crops on the land he leaves fallow during the fallow rotation, and he cannot
legally prevent them from doing so, and 2) even if no one appropriates the
fallow plots, they may still appropriate the surplus he produces from them,
preventing him from being able to enjoy said surplus. And yet, there may be
Pareto-improvements to be made. Let’s assume the innovation is purely one of
discovery, and has zero implementation cost, and it would increase average
annual production by δ, and
that the farmer currently is living at subsistence level, so his ‘surplus’
after implementation would be δ. Now, suppose
the cost the farmer’s neighbor foregoing plotting on the farmer’s fallow plots
is γ (this cost is due to the neighbor having to take the time to find other
arable land and the decreased yield he will obtain on inferior land that he
might plan on instead of the farmer’s fallow plots). Assuming the farmer’s
neighbor is the only threat to the fallowness of the farmer’s fallow plots, as
long as γ < δ, then the
farmer exchanging some fraction of δ that is > γ in return for his forbearance will be Pareto-efficient.
In fact, we may generalize this situation, and posit that as long as the cost
of innovation, α, is less than δ – γ, it is Pareto efficient for the farmer
to implement the innovation and make the necessary to retain exclusive rights
to use the land (or other resource) necessary for the implementation of the
innovation by making non-use contracts with other potential users of the
relevant resource(s).
So, the farmer has found he can make a Pareto-optimal
exchange with his neighbor that allows him to increase productivity and enjoy
some of the surplus, while allowing his neighbors to enjoy some of the surplus
as well. However, an obvious question emerges: what is to keep the parties of
these contracts pledging not to make use of the (legally, still socially owned)
resources from reneging on their end of the bargain? Or, alternatively, if the
party promising a portion of his surplus in exchange for guarantee of non-use
from others reneges on the promise to give ove some of the surplus? These
contracts, I’ve established, are not enforceable under law. The answer, in
essence, is credibility. The willingness of one to promise to exchange one’s
non-use in return for a share of the surplus in the future from a producer
depends on the trustworthiness of the producer. Conversely, the willingness of
a producer who thinks he can increase production in some manner if guaranteed
exclusive use to a resource to make a contract with other parties ensuring
their non-use – and therefore his willingness to implement his
production-enhancing endeavor – depends on the trustworthiness of the
presumptive non-users. At first, there will be high transaction costs due to
uncertainty, since no one will have a record of credibility in contract
adherence. However, once such contracts begin to take place (at first likely on
small scales with little overall risk), people will develop knowledge of who
around them is credible. And, just as rating systems for potential transaction
participants develop in the real world (Amazon user ratings being an example),
they may develop in our hypothetical world. These rating systems could serve as
the basis establishing market prices for the purchase of either future
surpluses from ‘producers’ or ‘investors’ in resources, or of non-use
commitments from potential users. Indeed, probability of use may itself be
priced into these transactions. For example, one would likely pay one’s
neighbor a greater amount to forego use than someone who lives a mile away. One
may, if one is extremely risk averse, pay some amount of the prospective future
surplus for forbearance even to people who live far away.
If sufficient technology exists, sophisticated markets could
emerge in which everyone could exchange the promise of non-use for all
resources in the world they have little interest in or expectation of using in
exchange for a share in the ‘general surplus.’ Such exchanges could be in the
form of promises of bundles of goods or services, or in some form of currency.
It could be commodity currency, or promissory notes redeemed for some
ubiquitously used commodity. In any case, a form of money economy would likely
replace pure barter, especially in an advanced society. Another important
phenomenon that would likely emerge: the willingness of people to engage in
transactions with people who have poor credibility in recorded contracts or even people who refuse to participate
in the market for such contracts will dwindle. This is because the more
established and large the market becomes, the more opportunities will be
available for participants on either side of non-use-for-surplus contracts to
find credible buyers and sellers, and the less appealing it will become, comparatively
speaking, to engage in transactions with those with no record.
But can’t people who don’t participate in the market still
act as ‘free riders’ and simply take surpluses from others or use resources
others have promised not to use regardless? To some extent, yes. However, the
key factor limiting their ability to ‘free ride’ is information. In most cases,
the ability to partake of the surplus being generated, one must know it is
being produced. A producer will only inform those with whom he has non-use
contracts of the surplus he is producing, and they obviously have an incentive
to conceal its production from others lest they usurp their own claim to part
of the surplus. This concealment of information will put such free riders at a
material disadvantage, and their reduced capacity to partake of the ‘general
surplus’ will serve as a disincentive to free-ride, even from a purely
self-interested position.
To summarize my argument: If there are valid reasons – as I
think there clearly are – why one would desire, either for consumption or
production reasons – why many people would want to guarantee exclusive use
rights to land or other resources 1) for a definite length of time, 2) for the
duration of one’s lifetime (or the duration of some partnership, or other
conditional duration), or 3) in hereditary perpetuity (where the contractual
rights are passed on to whom one may bequest them), then the trajectory of
society will be toward one in which, practically speaking, private property
exists and is nearly ubiquitous. This is because almost all people have almost
no use for almost all resources in the world, and therefore would probably be
willing to commit to non-use for trivially small compensation for it (or
perhaps even to establish credibility so as to be able to sell non-us
commitment to resources potentially dearer to them at a higher price). What’s
more, those who effectively identify resources from which surpluses can be
produced will become progressively more adept at identifying such hidden potential
for surpluses, and will this practice will likely tend toward
professionalization, since activities for which productivity depends heavily on
domain information and experience tend to specialize over time. Such
professional surplus seekers will closely resemble the capitalists of the world
we live in. Furthermore, the ability to store and share information on
credibility of contract participants will serve to gradually increase the
number of these transactions, lead to the equilibration of market prices of
non-use, and create incentives against ‘free riding’ even for purely
self-interested agents. There is, moreover, no reason why a similar system of
legally unenforceable contracts aided by information markets would not function
for labor contracts as well. As such, only the freedom of individuals to
voluntarily agree to forego use of a resource, and the desire for exclusivity
in use, are necessary for a society in which all resources are socially owned
to ‘degenerate’ (or, in my opinion, evolve) into a system of de facto private property, in which
capitalists use subsume risks by making investments that use resources and
employ labor – in exchange for promise of material compensation - to generate
goods and services, which are in turn sold to consumers for a surplus. Legally
enforceable property rights are unnecessary, as private property – in essence,
right of exclusive use - can effectively be constructed negatively via non-use
contractual agreements with others. These property rights are, moreover, to the
net benefit of society, as the exchanges through which they develop are
Pareto-efficient and tend toward the allocation of resources toward those who
can make the most productive use of them in satisfying consumer demand.
Part 2. State Enforcement of Contracts as a
Means of Lowering Transaction Costs
One might argue that the evolution from social ownership to
de facto private ownership is
possible, but not inevitable, and perhaps not even likely. I would argue that
the history of private property the world over strongly suggests that the
emergence of private property I described above is in fact inevitable, and that
the emergence of legal, state-enforced property rights is a direct consequence
of this inevitability. Once contractual promises like the ones described above
have begun to occur in significant number, it will become apparent that it is
Kaldor-Hicks efficient to introduce alienability
into the system; that is to make contracts enforceable not merely through
restricting access to voluntary exchange (e.g., refusing to do business with
someone has a record of violating contracts), but by imposing punishment on
contract violators and/or requiring them, by force, to pay restitution.
It is worth noting that rise of alienable transactions in a
society need not derive from coercion. People will tend to voluntarily subject
themselves to ‘alienative’ transactions. This is because they reduce
transaction costs. The willingness to subject oneself to punishment on the
condition of breach of contract reduces, in the mind of the other party, the
likelihood that one will violate the terms; this in turn means he’ll be willing
to make the contract at a lower price if he’s the seller, or a higher price if
he’s the buyer. Therefore, one who intends to fulfil one’s end of the bargain –
unless there is significant uncertainty over whether one will be able to
regardless of intent – will have an incentive to prefer such an alienative
contract, as it allows one to buy at lower prices or sell at higher prices. In
fact, if the only risk is the unknowability of the other transaction
participants’ intentions, then the ‘community of the honest’ – all the people
who intend to abide by the contracts in which they participate – will have
obvious material incentives to always engage in alienative transaction, and
will collectively benefit from an increase in the occurrence of mutually
beneficial transactions and in the size of the sum of the surpluses generated
as a result. Even if there is a risk of not being able to fulfil one’s end of a
contract even if one has honest intentions (e.g., an investment may fail,
leaving one unable to pay back a debt), many will likely be willing to submit
to punishment for an unintentional breach of contract, reasoning that the cost
of the punishment is less than the cost of losing the opportunity to engage in
future transactions that would result from violating the conditional punishment
clause of the contract.
Of course, by construction, alienative contracts are
forbidden under our hypothetical social ownership-based system. But it is
important to realize that the state would almost certainly have to actively
suppress such contracts and take punitive action against those who engage in
them. Some individuals may aid the state in suppressing their would-be
punishers, but many would not because occasionally undergoing punishment (which
may of course imply be forced restitution) may be worth it to be able to engage
in more mutually beneficial transactions.
Overall, there is an unavoidable problem in the political
sustainability of the prohibition on alienative contracts: those who sincerely
seek to engage in mutually beneficial contracts will benefit from alienative
contracts, and will tend to pressure the state (a state would, I contend, be
necessary to enforce the prohibition on alienative contracts in the first
place) to remove such prohibitions. Those who have no interest in engaging in
alienative contracts and those who have no interest in participating in
economic transactions do not benefit from the prohibition, and would have no
interest in supporting it. The only group that would have an interest in the
prohibition of alienative contracts is people who intend to participate in
transactions and violate them. Unless this cohort is a large fraction of the
population, the state will face an uphill battle in maintaining the prohibition
on alienative contracts. Moreover, the state’s revenue would almost inevitable
depend on either the number of transactions that occur (or some subset of them)
or the total product of the economy (or some subset thereof), and since the
latter depends on the former, and the former is greater when alienative
contracts are permitted, the state itself will have a vested material interest
in permitting alienative contracts.
Even if no state exists, however, most of the population
will have a material incentive to indulge or permit the enforcement of fully
alienative contracts. That is, if one signs a contract in which a punishment is
specified as conditional on breach of contract, the general public has a vested
interest in tolerating the wronged party imposing the specified punishment on
the violator of the contract irrespective of whether he voluntarily submits to
it. The widespread enforcement of alienative contracts would increase the costs
of violating contracts and thereby reduce the uncertainty associated with them
for those intent on not violating
contracts. If the latter group makes up the majority of the population, then
the preponderance of society will most likely benefit from this practice and
tolerate if not encourage it.
Of course, a putatively wronged party cannot likely be
trusted to enforce its own contract. Especially when the punishment to be
imposed is forced restitution, one may have a material incentive to employ a
‘liberal’ definition of what constitutes breach of contract to justify
expropriating the other party. The employment of neutral third parties to
enforce contracts, and if necessary impose coercive punishment on violators,
therefore makes sense for rational economic agents. As with arguably most
industries, economies of scale likely apply, and there may be a natural
tendency toward monopoly – especially within a defined geographic region – in
contract enforcement. The entity I am describing may sound increasingly like a
state. There is, however, a missing ingredient: the enforcement of contracts
for which this neutral third party has not even been employed. Why would such
an entity, say, seek to punish all robbers in its area, regardless of whether
the victims have hired it to do so? The answer may resemble the answer to the
question of why a pizza delivery company would pave potholes in roads: it may
be worth it for an entity to render a public good when its private benefits
from doing so exceed its private costs. If a third party contract enforcer is
already employed by most of the residents of a town, region, or country, then
it is highly likely that a thief or scammer whose victim is not one of its
clients may yet victimize one of its clients in the future, incentivizing the
contract enforcer to impose punishments on all thieves and scammers in its
jurisdiction. Of course, then those within its jurisdiction who are not its
clients will be ‘free riders,’ and those who are clients, who make up the majority, will have both the incentive
and the political power to mandate everyone within its jurisdiction to become
its client – and pay the concomitant fees - to solve this ‘free rider’ problem.
Finally, the constant negotiation of terms with the third party contract
enforcer for specific contracts between individuals or firms bears its own
significant transaction costs. For many common contracts – such as simple
non-use commitments – it may be less costly to assume universal standards of
enforcement, punishment, and restitution for all clients/residents, and all
property (or at least all property of a given category) rather than negotiating
each contract individually. Thus, we arrive at what one might safely call a
state. The coercive or nonconsensual aspects of laws and the enforcement
thereof may be interpreted as ‘short cuts’ to enforcing the many contracts that
most people would want to engage in with their neighbors anyway, but in a
manner that avoids many of the transaction costs that would arise from having
to negotiate each inter-personal or inter-firm contract individually. The
preponderance of residents of the state’s jurisdiction may rationally tolerate
the cost of such ‘corner-cutting’ on the matter of obtaining consent – such as
mandating contribution to the maintenance of the state - because the cost of
maintaining the state tends to be less than the cost of having to constantly
negotiate and renegotiate innumerable contracts with everyone with whom one
engages in economic transactions, and with the state of course, and because the
reduction in uncertainty about one’s transaction partners’ intentions by the
state’s coercive actions outweighs the costs, relative to, say, having to rely
purely on completely voluntary transaction participant ratings systems. The
state’s raison d’etre – or at least, its raison d’etre qua giver and enforcer of laws - may thus be as simple as the
mitigation of transaction costs.
In his book, The Rise
of the West, Douglas North attributes the rather sudden economic expansion
in Western Europe during the 17th century – especially the Low
Countries and Britain – in large part to the cultivation of legal contract
enforcement. Exchange of goods and services occurred before such contract
enforcement, of course, and primitive markets existed in the form of traveling
fairs, where merchants of a particular trade – wine, textiles, etc. – would
sell goods together, exploiting what we would now call network effects. However,
market exchanges were a fairly small fraction of economy. The gradual
realization by states disproportionately dependent on exchange – states that
were hubs for international trade or early textile manufacturing, such as the
Netherlands, had a particularly strong incentive and the necessary economies of
scale to find it worthwhile to reduce the transaction costs inherent in the
uncertainty of contract adherence by assuming the role of enforcing such
contracts. As a direct result of this assumption of contract enforcement, the
more mutually beneficial contracts took place, raising the value of credible
contract enforcement by the state as a neutral third party even more. This
continuation of this ‘virtuous cycle’ was, in turn a major factor in the rapid
economic development on the eve of the industrial revolution of those countries
in which the state increasingly enforced alienative contracts – the Low
Countries and Britain, notable – relative to those nations that lagged in the
enforcement of commercial contracts and also outlawed many more forms of
voluntary contract as well and languished economically – such as France and
Spain. Indeed, the fact that a private property based system has arisen in
every successful society in the world, and what few societies can be found
where social ownership has prevailed being relegated to the margins of the global
economy, may be evidence of the irresistible economic gains to be made by the
vast majority of people from the fostering of private markets for – and
therefore ownership of – goods, capital, and resources in general.
My conclusion to the second part of this essay is that the
system of private property entailed by the enforcement of alienative contracts
by the state was not imposed in the interests of a class, but cultivated
gradually and spontaneously due to an emergent mutualistic relationship between
markets and the state. In particular,
there were net gains in production and well-being to be made by enfranchising a
neutral third party (a role existing states were best positioned to fill) with
a ‘monopoly on violence,’ a monopoly to be used to enforce contracts and reduce
the uncertainty of economic transaction. The cost of maintaining such a state
was likely less than the gains from reduced transaction costs. Discerning
readers may notice that what I’ve written here has a thoroughly Coasean ethos
to it. Indeed, what I have illustrated is essentially a ‘negative’ application
of Coase Theorem: one need not have private property for Coase Theorem to
apply; even where private property does not exist, resources will be optimally
allocated through the exchange of ‘negative ownership,’ or commitment not to
use, and only transaction costs inhibit this optimal allocation. And it is
because of these transaction costs that coercive third party enforcement of
contracts – e.g., enforcement by the state – can be economically productive by
reducing uncertainty-related transaction costs by more than the cost of
maintaining such third party enforcement.
Comments
Post a Comment